4.
In this perspective, the process of humanity’s
separation from nature and the latter’s subordination as a mere object of
appropriation signifies both a distortion of human cognitive interests
exclusively towards domination and a repression of the natural in man. This is
the paradox of the civilisatory process. In this development, the supposed
goal— a fully civilised humanity—becomes a mere means and is distorted and
brutalised by the instrument—reason—that is supposedly the means of liberation.
For Horkheimer and Adorno, the tragic mistake is the identification of the
subject with a distorted rational faculty of mere calculation and the
dissolution of all phenomena into the quantitative calculus of this faculty.
“Identity thinking” reduces everything alien to its own categories and thereby
eliminates all otherness and difference. A qualitatively different world is
transformed into one homogenous with the categories of reason. The human
attempt to preserve itself through increasingly knowledge requires an ascetic
suspension of appetites and the elimination of the other, of the non-identical.
Latent in this idea of self –preservation is the idea of the subjectivity as a
unified ratio. Increasing knowledge is identified with unified rationality in
terms of increasing coherence, systematisation and logic. By this means,
knowledge becomes autonomous, exclusively identified with a single faculty but
increasingly detached from the interests and other needs of the corporeal, natural
subject. The result is that the development of civilisation is a history not of
liberation but of increasingly domination of self, nature and others.
5.
The first social expression of this inversion of
ends and means is the primitive division of labour. The categories of logic
arose as ideal expressions of the original social relations of domination. The
order and hierarchy of concepts reflect the primitive social hierarchy. These
ideal categories serve as instruments of man’s attempt to report, order and
explain the surrounding environment in the interests of his own
self-preservation. While these categories were only a means, they preserved and
exemplified the irrational structure of domination. When thinking is understood
as mere self-identification, it is reduced to emptiness and formalism. A
specific mode of thought has been reified in just the same way that the
bourgeois commodity form expresses the permanent quest for equivalence. All
aspects of the external world outside the subject and nature within are reduced
to the thinking activity and terms of the subject, which becomes blind to its
own particularity and constructed character. It also marginalised the other
more reflective dimension of rationality. For abstract rationality, the
qualitative uniqueness of each particular phenomenon and situation is rendered
imperceptible and inexpressible. Abstract rationality treats every unique
historical situation as a repetition of what has already occurred. The single
and unique is obliterated by subordination to the lawfulness that allows them
to be subsumed by rational thought. This ideal of lawfulness is a perpetuation
of the ancient myth of eternal recurrence, which naturalises the present as an
eternal order.
6.
The radical meaning of this analysis is revealed in
the equation of the whole civilisatory process with the concept of
enlightenment. Here the concept of enlightenment is understood not as the
antithesis of myth but as a perpetuation of the innermost logic of the latter.
On this view, myth is originally nothing but the first version of
enlightenment. It is product of the human need to subordinate nature to its own
categories of regularity, order and explanation. Myth is the first instalment a process of evolving
enlightenment in which every worldview will have to submit itself to more
sophisticated cultural interpretations of rationality. On this reading, myth is
a form of enlightenment that cannot withstand its own ongoing enhancement. The
program of enlightenment is thus the ongoing destruction of the rational
pretensions of all previous forms of social explanation-magic, myth, and
religion. However, this program of critical destruction of the past forms of
rational explanation is ultimately nihilistic. It eventually annihilates
precisely those concepts, on which the Enlightenment had based itself and for
which it had struggled. These values--truth, reason, freedom and justice—also
eventually succumb to the new more rigorous standards of contemporary
scientific analysis. Under critical analysis these values are revealed as
illusions, as myths, which can now be demoted to the level of magic. Whereas
the enlightenment believed reason to be an anthropological constant and truth
“correspondence” to an existing objective structure of the world, contemporary
analysis empties out the idea of a “rational faculty” to reveal nothing but a
variable cultural construct without substantive content, the product of a
contingent and idiosyncratic historical odyssey, whereas “truth” is merely a
property of sentences with no direct purchase on the world; freedom and justice
are value concepts that have no legitimate place in a scientific worldview.
This is the dialectic of enlightenment. Each new form of enlightenment destroys
its predecessor and discards it as just another myth. However, the most modern
variant of enlightenment--scientific positivism-- attempts to exempt itself
from the fate of all its predecessors. On its view scientific method is immune
from this fate of perpetual self-critique. As the most recent philosophical
reading of the method of science positivism bases itself on “facts’ but is
unwilling to enquire into the ground or the basis of those facts. In
methodologically excluding such questions, it ignores its own historical
pre-conditions and eternalises the existing social world as the eternal or
natural substratum of all experience. This invests existing social power with
the same absolute status that was once claimed by the old metaphysical truths.
For Horkheimer and Adorno, the desire to avoid critical examination is
symptomatic of the ideological limitation and weakness of positivism. It
signifies that this most scientific version of enlightenment has its own
metaphysical bias. This denial of self-reflectivity is, for Horkheimer and
Adorno, the perpetuation of myth. To absolutise the contemporary version of
reason and to equate it with the adoption of quantitative, mathematical
procedures is to convert means into ends and to lose sight of a rationality
that is anything more than mere calculation.
7.
What is the real purpose of this critique of
civilisation as a process of constant critical enlightenments? On one level,
this was ideology critique. The authors critique the modern faith in progress
and especially its failure to relativise its own claim to rationality. But, on
another level, it does not stop at mere ideology critique. Here is the attempt
to diagnose what the authors consider to be a new modern form of domination,
characterised by new degrees of alienation, depersonalisation and administrative
repression. Here the authors offer a crucial departure from the critical theory
formulated by Horkheimer in the 1930’s. They depict a society no longer in
crisis and no longer generating its own immanent forces of resistance. This
society had overcome the threatened economic collapse by political,
administrative cultural means. The “totally administered society”, a society
where economic, political and cultural power and authority have been fused into
a unified system, had been able to expunge all historical subjectivity surplus
to the requirements of maintaining profitable, capitalist reproduction. Here
again we have the paradoxical inversion of means and ends. Historical
subjectivity, supposedly the highest achievement of the process of
civilisation, is negated in favour of the functional requirements of the
totally administered society.
9. With
the control and manipulation of even the major social bearer of resistance to
bourgeois society, with the pacification of the working class through
incremental improvements in living standards and a stupefying mass culture, all
critical momentum is lost and critique survives only in the exceptional
isolated individual who have not surrendered their critical faculties to the
illusion of a integrated, rational organization. This gloomy picture of a
totally administered society typified by an underlying conformity and absence
of social resistance has often led to the authors being accused of cultural
aristocratism and pessimism. Certainly Dialectic
of Enlightenment does almost invite misinterpretation. While Horkheimer and
Adorno censure all philosophy of history, they simultaneously seem to construct
one of their own, only theirs’ is in reverse. Rather than viewing history as a progressive process, they
construct a grand narrative of disasters, from “the sling shot to the atom
bomb” as Adorno was to characterise it later, with the contemporary victory of
an especially sophisticated instrumental rationality and overly refined
domination of containment. But this is not the simple inconsistency it might at
first appear. At various points, the authors do speak about missed historical
opportunities for emancipation. However, these opportunities were bungled and
the fully administered society seems devised to kill subjective resistance
before it can even emerge. The ambiguity in Horkheimer and Adorno’s position
make it hard to divine just where they stand. They consciously employ extreme
formulations and striking contradictory images to redouble critical energies
and to illuminate what they perceive to be the real truth behind the appearance
of progress. Deprived of a concrete social bearer of critique, these authors
make a strategic withdrawal to philosophy and even art. Horkheimer withdraws
from running the Institute after its return to Germany and becomes more
politically conservative. The
later Adorno will resort to a more aesthetic mode of argumentation and relying
less on the categories and coherence of philosophical theory, which, according
to him, has now become contaminated by instrumental reason and the logic of
domination. While the later Adorno as Head of the Institute was heavily engaged
in a range of projects, overseeing empirical studies and becoming a major
public intellectual, he did not fundamentally re-evaluate his essentially
negative view of modernity even while he realised that the liberal democracy
being created in Germany was not identical to the other totalitarian forms.